Unmanned scouts are ideal for
performing the prewar
‘tattletale’ role that until now could only be accomplished by manned platforms.
These vehicles might allow the opponent to persistently cover a wider area or
track a particular contact longer than might be possible if only manned scouts
were used. They would obviously also avoid exposing manned scouts to
interception by the defender.
It is highly likely that U.S.
rules of engagement during a crisis would preclude destroying an opponent’s
manned scout in the absence of high confidence indications and warning that the
opponent intended an imminent attack. U.S. use of non-kinetic means to
‘neutralize’ a manned scout would likely be limited as well. It is far less
clear, though, that neutralizing or destroying an unmanned scout would carry
similar escalation risks or otherwise set unacceptable escalatory precedents.
Consider how Russia shot
down several Georgian unmanned aerial scouts prior to the 2008 war, or how
Iran shot
at (and
possibly also commandeered) U.S. unmanned aerial scouts over the past few
years. Crisis circumstances matter, but it is worth noting that none of these
cases resulted in anything more than diplomatic protests by the victims. These
cases actually establish a decent international precedent regarding the
legitimate bounds of a country’s response to the loss of its unmanned scouts.
Granted, neither Russia nor Iran nor any other potential U.S. adversary would
necessarily react along the lines of how Georgia or the U.S. did. Nevertheless,
far less stigma (and international scorn) attaches to killing robots than
manned platforms.
Therefore, as I noted in my
article:
A defender might
declare exclusion areas during a crisis within which any detected unmanned
system would be neutralized; enforcement of these areas might well not precipitate
drastic escalation by the other side...A potential adversary could overcome
this threat by placing unmanned systems under close manned escort, but that
would undercut the rationale for using unmanned, vice manned, reconnaissance
systems to increase search volume and on-station time per sortie. Also, it is
not clear how a potential adversary could respond without disproportionate
escalation if a defender neutralized the unmanned system by close-in jamming or
other nonkinetic means. The point is worth study through war gaming. (Pg. 99,
115)
Depending upon how an unmanned
scout was neutralized, the opponent might not even know within an actionable
period of time whether an onboard malfunction or ‘external causes’ resulted in
the loss of communications with the vehicle. This could support a U.S. ability
to assert plausible deniability if need be. There would be a risk, however,
that the opponent might conclude U.S. forces were operating in or near the area
the scout was passing through when communications with it were lost. This might
entice the opponent to focus its surveillance and reconnaissance resources on
that area. All the same, if the U.S. had in fact declared a sufficiently broad
exclusion area for the opponent’s unmanned vehicles, an overall U.S. deception
and concealment plan might allow for disruption or even destruction of the
opponent’s unmanned scouts near a specific location to create an impression
that ‘something of value’ was nearby even when the actual U.S. or allied units
being concealed were somewhere else entirely. Of course, nothing would prevent
the opponent from pursuing similar ends via similar tactics.
I would submit that if war
gaming and historical case study analysis find that the crisis stability risks
of attacks against unmanned scouts would be tolerable, and if the resulting
legitimization of equivalent attacks against U.S. unmanned systems would be
acceptable, then it might be worthwhile for American diplomacy to advance
unmanned scout neutralization (or destruction if the scout is outside the
opponent’s internationally-recognized sovereign boundaries) as an international
norm. This would not mean that the U.S. would automatically take such steps
during a particular crisis—only that U.S. political and military leaders would reserve
the option of taking them. If the opponent raised his forces’ combat readiness
postures in response, that would be still be a preferable—and most likely more
manageable—consequence than allowing the opponent to retain a high-confidence
targeting picture that could decisively tilt him towards a decision to strike
first.
The irony in all this is
that it may incentivize potential adversaries to go 'back to the future.'
If a potential adversary expects that U.S. forces will neutralize
unmanned scouts without hesitation, then he may opt to return
the brink-of-war tattletale role to manned scouts under the assumptions about
U.S. rules of engagement during a crisis that I mentioned earlier. So the moral of the story may very well be: don't operate high campaign-value platforms in locations during crises where they would not be able to evade contact with the opponent's manned scouts for long. Instead, preserve those platforms in locations where the opponent cannot scout effectively, or contact with any manned scouts can be quickly and enduringly broken. And remember that whatever the opponent's prewar escalation dominance advantages of using manned scouts may be, those advantages evaporate once U.S. rules of engagement are relaxed upon the outbreak of open hostilities.
The views expressed herein
are solely those of the author and are presented in his personal capacity. They
do not reflect the official positions of Systems Planning and Analysis, and to
the author’s knowledge do not reflect the policies or positions of the U.S.
Department of Defense, any U.S. armed service, or any other U.S. Government
agency.
No comments:
Post a Comment